Examlex
Julia Annas: Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing
Annas begins by describing the orthodox way of doing ethics in the twentieth century. The standard aim of ethical theory, she maintains, has been the search for a decision procedure - i.e., a specific set of instructions for how to act that applies to everyone in the same way. Annas believes that this "manual model" of ethics should be rejected, and replaced with the approach offered by virtue ethics.
Before turning to her virtue-based approach, Annas offers three main criticisms of the manual model of ethics. First, the manual model predicts there could be moral savants. But, unlike in mathematics, there are no moral savants. Children are moral idiots. Second, the manual model makes possible a person brilliant at giving moral advice, while having a character and values that are morally detestable. But this, Annas claims, is absurd. Third, and most importantly by Annas's lights, the manual model of morality give specific and decisive answers concerning what we should do - i.e., we are told what to do. But we do not want morality dictating our lives around. Aren't we, Annas questions, losing an important sense in which we should be making our own decisions? Virtue ethics, Annas claims, avoids these problems.
According to Annas, we should think of becoming virtuous on the lines of learning to be a builder. To become a better builder you start by picking a role model and copying what she does. Slowly, you learn to build better, engaging in the activity in a way which is less dependent on the examples of others and expresses more understanding of your own. Finally, you progress from piecemeal understanding of building to a more unified understanding of building. You have, that is, become a good builder. Being morally good, Annas argues, proceeds in this same way. We look to virtuous human beings, and the practical wisdom they demonstrate, so that we too can become virtuous - doing the right thing, for the right reasons, with the right motive. In short, we learn to live virtuous lives by acting as the virtuous person acts, until we can grasp what virtue demands for ourselves. Thus, just as what is right for one acquiring a skill depends on her stage of development, the morally right action differs depending on where the agent is in her development of a virtuous character.
-According to Annas, the clearest example of a moral theory that produces a decision procedure telling us what to do is:
Mesopotamia
An ancient region located in the eastern Mediterranean, bounded by the Tigris and Euphrates rivers, known as one of the cradles of civilization where writing and urban culture first appeared.
Sacrifice Ritual
Ceremonial acts performed in various cultures and religions involving the offering of gifts, and often the life of an animal or symbolic item, to a deity or higher power for the purpose of divine favor or atonement.
Aryan Religion
The religious beliefs and practices associated with the Indo-European peoples known as Aryans, precursor to major religions such as Hinduism.
Soma
In Vedic tradition, Soma is a ritual drink of importance among the early Indians, also referred to a deity associated with this drink.
Q3: Foot claims that one can refute a
Q3: According to Annas, if a moral theory
Q3: Hare defines ethics as:<br>A) the attempt to
Q6: According to Korsgaard, what is the relationship
Q8: According to Timmerman, commonsense morality permits us,
Q8: Kant claims that an act has moral
Q15: Wolf argues that moral sainthood does not
Q19: Annas argues that the manual model of
Q26: According to the third principle of equity,
Q28: Hanson acknowledges the existence of social injustices