Examlex
Judith Jarvis Thomson: The Trolley Problem
Consider the following case: A bystander can pull a switch, turning a runaway trolley off of a track on which it will kill five innocent people, and onto a track on which it will kill one innocent person. Call this case Bystander at the Switch. Now consider a different case: A surgeon can kill one of his perfectly healthy patients and use his organs to save five other dying patients. Call this case Transplant. In both of these cases, the agent is presented with an opportunity to save five lives for the cost of one. Yet most people believe that, while it is permissible to turn the trolley in Bystander at the Switch, it is impermissible to operate in Transplant. But what explains these different verdicts?
To answer this question, Thomson examines three proposals: killing v. letting die, using someone as a mere means, and the concept of rights. She argues against the first two proposals and in favor of the third. Killing v. letting die, Thomson claims, is too blunt an instrument to distinguish between these cases. Indeed, those endorsing the killing v. letting die distinction should, since bystander would be killing someone by flipping the switch, find bystander's act impermissible. But that, she argues, looks like the wrong verdict. Thomson insists that relying on using someone as a mere means also will not do the required work. Consider a "loop variant" of Bystander at the Switch, where the tracks do not diverge but circle back. Imagine that the five on the straight track are thin, but thick enough so that although all five will be killed if the trolley goes straight, the bodies of the five will stop it. and it will hence not reach the one. On the other hand, the one on the right-hand track is fat. so fat that his body will by itself stop the trolley, and the trolley will hence not reach the five. The loop variant ensures that Bystander must use the one as a means only, but adding the loop hardly seems to make a moral difference - even with the loop, Bystander acts permissibly by flipping the switch. This leaves the concept of rights.
Thomson argues that we can explain the different verdicts in Bystander at the Switch and Transplant by the following two features. First, the bystander saves the five by making something that threatens them instead threaten one. Second, the bystander does not do this saving by means which infringe any of the one's rights. These two features, Thomson concludes, allows us to justify our different intuitions in these two cases (and other difficult cases) .
-According to Thomson, one way to test if we are using someone, X, as a mere means is by asking:
Telephone Triage
The process of evaluating and prioritizing patients' conditions over the phone to direct them to the appropriate level of care.
Prescription Renewals
The process of obtaining an additional supply of a previously prescribed medication, often requiring approval from the original prescribing healthcare provider.
Regular Schedule
A planned or systematic arrangement of tasks, activities, or events, often set to occur at specific times.
Confirm Information
The act of verifying the accuracy and reliability of given data or details.
Q2: According to Thomson, if the bystander turns
Q4: Deterrence, which is a derivative of eighteenth-century
Q9: A _ is an order to stop
Q10: According to the text, the interpretation of
Q10: What did Cesare Becarria believe?<br>A) That punishment
Q10: What do you think is the best
Q20: Rachels holds that a fundamental requirement of
Q20: According to Marquis, contractarians cannot account for
Q22: According to Regan, modern crop production makes
Q27: Unlike Moore, Sinnott-Armstrong argues that we can