Examlex
Judith Jarvis Thomson: The Trolley Problem
Consider the following case: A bystander can pull a switch, turning a runaway trolley off of a track on which it will kill five innocent people, and onto a track on which it will kill one innocent person. Call this case Bystander at the Switch. Now consider a different case: A surgeon can kill one of his perfectly healthy patients and use his organs to save five other dying patients. Call this case Transplant. In both of these cases, the agent is presented with an opportunity to save five lives for the cost of one. Yet most people believe that, while it is permissible to turn the trolley in Bystander at the Switch, it is impermissible to operate in Transplant. But what explains these different verdicts?
To answer this question, Thomson examines three proposals: killing v. letting die, using someone as a mere means, and the concept of rights. She argues against the first two proposals and in favor of the third. Killing v. letting die, Thomson claims, is too blunt an instrument to distinguish between these cases. Indeed, those endorsing the killing v. letting die distinction should, since bystander would be killing someone by flipping the switch, find bystander's act impermissible. But that, she argues, looks like the wrong verdict. Thomson insists that relying on using someone as a mere means also will not do the required work. Consider a "loop variant" of Bystander at the Switch, where the tracks do not diverge but circle back. Imagine that the five on the straight track are thin, but thick enough so that although all five will be killed if the trolley goes straight, the bodies of the five will stop it. and it will hence not reach the one. On the other hand, the one on the right-hand track is fat. so fat that his body will by itself stop the trolley, and the trolley will hence not reach the five. The loop variant ensures that Bystander must use the one as a means only, but adding the loop hardly seems to make a moral difference - even with the loop, Bystander acts permissibly by flipping the switch. This leaves the concept of rights.
Thomson argues that we can explain the different verdicts in Bystander at the Switch and Transplant by the following two features. First, the bystander saves the five by making something that threatens them instead threaten one. Second, the bystander does not do this saving by means which infringe any of the one's rights. These two features, Thomson concludes, allows us to justify our different intuitions in these two cases (and other difficult cases).
-Thomson argues that, by flipping the switch, bystander does not infringe any rights of the one track workman.
Pivotal
Crucial or critically important, often in the context of events or decisions that have the power to affect outcomes significantly.
Vygotsky
A Russian psychologist who contributed to developmental psychology and education with his theories on social interaction and cognitive development.
Language
A system of communication used by a particular community or country, involving the use of words in a structured and conventional way.
Scaffolding
A teaching method that involves providing support to students or learners through various techniques as they are introduced to new concepts, reducing support as they become more proficient.
Q5: In Powell v. Alabama, the Court overturned
Q9: Explain Rachels's example of infants with Down's
Q9: Marquis claims that to solve the abortion
Q9: According to Foot, the crucial issue in
Q9: In Witherspoon v. Illinois (1968), the Supreme
Q11: According to Davis, men often tend to
Q16: The death penalty was used in England
Q16: The Argument from Queerness has two parts:
Q18: Mackie claims that if something were objectively
Q19: Since Furman, there have been no more