Examlex
James Rachels: Active and Passive Euthanasia
Active euthanasia is the intentional termination of a patient's life by another person, for the sake of relieving the pain and suffering of the patient. Passive euthanasia is the cessation of medical assistance needed to prolong a patient's life, again performed for the sake of relieving pain and suffering. The conventional doctrine in medical ethics is that whereas passive euthanasia is sometimes morally permissible, active euthanasia never is. Rachels argues that the conventional doctrine faces serious objections, and cannot be correct.
Rachels raises two objections to the conventional doctrine. The first is that the purpose of euthanasia is to alleviate pain and suffering, and in many cases active euthanasia can serve this function much more efficiently than passive euthanasia. Thus, if a decision has been made to employ euthanasia, active euthanasia is preferable to passive euthanasia. Rachels's second objection is that the conventional doctrine leads to decisions about life and death being made on morally irrelevant grounds. For example, passive euthanasia is sometimes employed on infants born with Down's syndrome who would require a simple surgery to survive. Such infants are allowed to die not because they require surgery, but because they have Down's syndrome. The decision to euthanize such infants depends on the irrelevant fact that they require a simple operation.
The acceptance of the conventional doctrine is often grounded in the view that killing is intrinsically worse than letting die. Against this, Rachels imagines two cases that are exactly alike in every respect, except that one involves killing and the other involves letting die. In the first case, Smith drowns his young cousin to gain his inheritance. In the second case, Jones, like Smith, intends to kill his young cousin, but ends up (because of a slippery bath tub) merely watching him drown. Rachels claims that the two men behave equally wrongly, and that this shows there is no morally relevant distinction between killing and letting die. The distinction between killing and letting die thus cannot be used to support the conventional doctrine
-According to Rachels, if a doctor lets a patient die for humane reasons:
Dominant Alleles
Alleles that mask the effect of other alleles for the same gene in heterozygous individuals, determining the phenotype.
Recessive Alleles
Genetic variations that must be present in two copies (homozygous) to express a trait, as opposed to dominant alleles that require only one copy.
Epistasis
An interaction between genes where the presence or absence of alleles of one gene influences the expression of another gene.
Alleles
Alleles are alternative forms of a gene that arise by mutation and are found at the same place on a chromosome, contributing to genetic variation in populations.
Q3: Taylor claims that the two types of
Q4: Wolf refers to the point of view
Q5: Korsgaard's "internalist requirement" states that:<br>A) practical reasons
Q9: Crouch describes how some women have taken
Q10: What, according to Midgley, is moral isolationism?
Q13: According to the conventional doctrine:<br>A) active euthanasia
Q15: One example of bad constitutive moral luck
Q27: According to Arpaly, an agent with a
Q30: Nagel claims that the actual results of
Q30: In modern moral philosophy, the priority accorded