Examlex
Judith Jarvis Thomson: The Trolley Problem
Consider the following case: A bystander can pull a switch, turning a runaway trolley off of a track on which it will kill five innocent people, and onto a track on which it will kill one innocent person. Call this case Bystander at the Switch. Now consider a different case: A surgeon can kill one of his perfectly healthy patients and use his organs to save five other dying patients. Call this case Transplant. In both of these cases, the agent is presented with an opportunity to save five lives for the cost of one. Yet most people believe that, while it is permissible to turn the trolley in Bystander at the Switch, it is impermissible to operate in Transplant. But what explains these different verdicts?
To answer this question, Thomson examines three proposals: killing v. letting die, using someone as a mere means, and the concept of rights. She argues against the first two proposals and in favor of the third. Killing v. letting die, Thomson claims, is too blunt an instrument to distinguish between these cases. Indeed, those endorsing the killing v. letting die distinction should, since bystander would be killing someone by flipping the switch, find bystander's act impermissible. But that, she argues, looks like the wrong verdict. Thomson insists that relying on using someone as a mere means also will not do the required work. Consider a "loop variant" of Bystander at the Switch, where the tracks do not diverge but circle back. Imagine that the five on the straight track are thin, but thick enough so that although all five will be killed if the trolley goes straight, the bodies of the five will stop it. and it will hence not reach the one. On the other hand, the one on the right-hand track is fat. so fat that his body will by itself stop the trolley, and the trolley will hence not reach the five. The loop variant ensures that Bystander must use the one as a means only, but adding the loop hardly seems to make a moral difference - even with the loop, Bystander acts permissibly by flipping the switch. This leaves the concept of rights.
Thomson argues that we can explain the different verdicts in Bystander at the Switch and Transplant by the following two features. First, the bystander saves the five by making something that threatens them instead threaten one. Second, the bystander does not do this saving by means which infringe any of the one's rights. These two features, Thomson concludes, allows us to justify our different intuitions in these two cases (and other difficult cases).
-Thomson claims that the stringency of the right helps distinguish the Fat Man case from certain variants of Bystander at the Switch. What is Thomson's argument for relying on the stringency of the rights in question? Do you find this argument sustainable? Explain your answer.
Visible Wavelengths
The portion of the electromagnetic spectrum that is visible to the human eye, ranging approximately from 380 to 740 nanometers.
Inhibitory Area
A region in the nervous system that decreases the likelihood of a neuron firing, reducing activity in neural circuits.
Hypercomplex Cortical Cells
Neurons in the visual cortex that respond to specific characteristics of visual stimuli, such as the length or angle of an object.
Lateral Geniculate Cells
Neurons located in the lateral geniculate nucleus of the thalamus, playing a crucial role in visual processing by relaying information from the retina to the visual cortex.
Q1: Singer claims that his principle:<br>A) takes no
Q1: In the United States, the first recorded
Q2: Davis claims that gender roles and social
Q4: The 6th Amendment specifies the right to
Q8: In the penalty phase, the Court has
Q12: What does the Equal Protection Clause stand
Q17: According to Singer's view, the "Drowning Child"
Q19: In Smith v. Cain, the Court said
Q20: Allowing judges to override a jury and
Q30: As is evident in this early ruling,